16 October 2002 Democratic culture and extremist
Islam Werner
Schiffauer
Are Islam and democracy
incompatible? The evolution of a radical Turkish
Islamic group in Germany suggests that the pursuit
of ‘fundamentalist’ goals can itself create the
space for a rational appraisal of tradition. By
seeking truth in origin and scripture rather than
history, successive generations of Islamists may
be drawn – even despite themselves – towards a
more flexible commitment to a network society of
social individuals. This may not yet be democracy;
but it is reformation. |
|
When the Caliphate State led by Metin Kaplan, the
most radical group of political Islam in Turkey, was
banned on 5 December 2001, one of its supporters said on
camera: ‘If one is a Muslim, one is not a democrat. If
one is a democrat, one is not a Muslim.’
Democracy is here condemned by these believers in a
very literal sense. The supporters of the Caliphate
State regard democracy as the embodiment of the rule of
polytheism. This is equated with the rule of evil as
such. Thus, some members of the community went so far as
to see in democracy the deccal, the Antichrist
himself, who also appears in the final battle between
the good and evil of Islamic eschatology.
It might be thought that this is all that needs to be
said on the subject of democratic culture and extremist
Islam. I believe, however, that this subject is more
complex than such explicit statements imply. My argument
is this: the internal logic of the fundamentalist
gesture itself gives rise to developments which call it
into question and, under favourable circumstances, can
transcend it from within. In order to elaborate this
thesis I would like to examine the radical critique of
democracy in the Kaplan community and to clarify what
conceptions of individual and society it is based
on.
Discontent with democracy, and the Islamic
alternative
My interlocutors in the Kaplan community were imbued
with a vision of unity. ‘Once one has understood, that
ultimately everything is one, then one has understood
Islam.’ The idea of a single, all-encompassing
God is combined with the idea of a single
undivided community. It finds ritual expression in the
so-called five pillars of Islam: the confessional
formula (‘I testify, that there is no God but Allah, and
I testify, that Mohammed is God’s messenger’), the
ritual prayer at five fixed times of the day, the
requirement to be charitable, the requirement to fast,
and the pilgrimage to Mecca.
This unity is not an unstructured one. The ideal of
the inner structure can be exemplified by the star motif
of Islamic art. The illustration reproduced here shows
an inlay work on a 16th century Koran folding
lectern.
This star motif always seemed to me like a visual
rendering of a social and political vision. The societal
units interlock. Each unit – family, kinship group,
professional group, community, neighbourhood, enterprise
– is related to the whole, just like one of the larger
or smaller elements of the star motif to the pattern as
a whole. They form, as one would say today, a network.
The peace of society depends on the balance of the
elements.
Attention to boundaries plays a special role in the
preservation of the balance. Boundaries must never be
absolute, precisely because this would make the
interlocking and internal interpenetration impossible.
The ideal is not to supersede, to dissolve boundaries,
but to deal wisely with them. Dissolution is associated
with fitne – chaos, disorder.
In everyday life, this culture of the boundary is
expressed by a refined and elaborated ritualism; the
sphere of the other is observed and respected.
The idea of jihad is inscribed in this vision.
Jihad means ‘unceasing endeavour’ – and only one
meaning of jihad should be translated as ‘holy
war’. Ultimately jihad is directed at forces that
want to disturb the balance of the social order. At the
level of the individual, jihad means the battle
against the nefis (desire, egoism), which does
not accept the boundaries and calls them into question –
here, therefore, jihad means work on the self.
At the level of society it is the will to power, to
exploitation and expansion, which does not heed
boundaries and thereby calls the balance (and ultimately
the beautiful order) into question. In this case there
is a requirement of active resistance – if need be the
Muslim is called upon to take up arms. The Christian
idea of a principled profession of non-violence was
always very alien to my interlocutors, though the use of
force was only legitimate as defence. The resistance
both to the nefis and to usurpation appeared to
them to be prescribed by reason. They emphasised the
earthly responsibility for the maintenance of the
beautiful and rational order.
This Islamic vision of a network society forms the
background to their critique of parliamentary democracy.
The core of their arguments is that parliamentary
democracy is based on a culture of conflict; the
formation of opinion takes place in corporately
constituted groups, the parties, which form opinion
internally and then enter into debate with one another.
They are exclusive, to a certain extent autonomous and
can exist independently. They constitute distinct
identities. In such bodies the relationship of inside
and outside is fundamentally different from that in the
Islamic vision of the network.
Thus, the democratic culture of conflict implies the
sceptical idea of duality, as against the optimistic
idea of unity. Since no one owns the truth, regulated
forms of dispute must be established. Islamicist
dissatisfaction with this model is based on its
predisposition to discord, strife, and sham conflicts.
Against this, they evoke the dream of a scholars’
republic. Conflicts that arose were to be solved by
reference to the Koran, by obtaining a legal report, a
fatwa. The weight of such a report is
substantially dependent on the personal authority of the
issuer. Thus, unlike a court judgment, the legal opinion
given is only binding on someone who acknowledges this
authority. But personal authority develops out of the
free play of forces. What political Muslims have in
mind, therefore, is a scholars’ republic or a legal
opinion state.
The tension between theory and practice
How to implement this rigorous vision? If we now look
at the actual situation in the miniature universe of the
Islamicist communities in Germany, a noteworthy contrast
between doctrine and reality is immediately apparent.
From the start, several communities disputed the way in
which the social and political vision of Islam might be
advanced. It was interesting that there was no open
discussion and no openly conducted dispute about these
differences; but below the surface no holds were barred.
The early years, especially, of the establishment of
Islam in Germany, that is, from about 1968–1985, were
characterised by splits within mosques and by hostile
takeovers of mosque associations by competing
organisations. In other words, there were deep divisions
in German Islam. This was a problem, above all, for
Muslims themselves, who were very well aware of the
contrast between reality and beautiful ideal. They
tended to explain this in terms of human weakness and
inconsistency. I had the impression, however, that the
splitting was precisely a result of the consistency with
which they struggled to establish unity.
A small everyday observation encapsulates the
problems of the Islamic culture of conflict. In 1988, I
and my acquaintances from the Kaplan community called on
the Milli Görü community, from which the Kaplan
community had split off five years earlier. We were
courteously received as visitors. I was allowed to put
my questions, the hodja replied, my acquaintances
listened to him politely and agreed with everything with
a ‘tabii, tabii’ (‘of course, of course’).
To an outsider it would have presented a picture of
complete harmony; yet outside, the mood changed. The
hodja’s answers were torn to pieces. The whole
thing culminated in the sentence: ‘Did you hear, how
disrespectful he was of the other communities. That is
exactly why we left.’
I was told that there were questions I really should
have asked, in order to show up my opposite number. My
companions’ restraint inside the mosque reflects the
respect for boundaries. While in the other’s space, one
listens to him. To contradict him would violate the
rules of courtesy. Criticism may only be expressed when
one is outside again. The sociological problem of such
an ideal is obvious: an open argument is associated with
a rupture, with serious offence. ‘Divergence of opinion
[is] perceived as weakening the group and it [is] better
... to expel the oppositional group and let it go its
own way if it is too strong. Dissent is interpreted as
trauma, as a kind of terrible situation, because it
recalls the violence in Mecca before the triumph of the
one,’ writes Fatema Mernissi.
Islam within democracy: two routes
A historical sketch of two distinct communities of
Islam in Germany illustrates the argument I am making.
In 1984, Cemaleddin Kaplan broke with Milli Görü, the
European offshoot of what was then Necmettin Erbakan’s
Welfare Party. At the time, Milli Görü stood for the
parliamentary road to theocracy.
Cemaleddin Kaplan thought this route unrealistic,
especially given the experience of the state of
emergency in Turkey (1980–1983). If an Islamic party
grew strong enough to take power, the army would
inevitably intervene. Kaplan (whose doctrine developed
under the influence of the pioneering Islamicist
thinkers Al-Maududi and Sayyid Qutb) saw this dilemma as
revealing inconsistency in applying the ideal of unity.
The Islamic vision, he thought, cannot only be taken
seriously as a goal; the everyday political
struggle must also be guided by Islamic principles.
Thus, the party should be replaced by an open,
inclusive movement. The return to the original ideals
would allow the unfortunate split between the
communities to be overcome, leading to a stronger
position; the movement would take over the government in
Turkey and ultimately allow the Caliphate – the office
of the leader of all believers, which was abolished by
the Turkish revolution – to be restored.
Kaplan failed – even in his attempt to bring together
the believers (let alone his ultimate goal of taking
power). He wanted to overcome the division of Islam, but
instead did more to widen it than anyone else. This was
because his vision conflicted with the immanent logic of
the social. He failed to take account of the inertia of
established institutions. Contrary to his expectations,
masses of believers did not go over to him.
Kaplan was thus presented with a dilemma. A
charismatic, open movement must either take off – or it
disappears. Facing defeat, Kaplan tried to save his
programme, by turning the open, inclusive movement into
a sect and increasingly radicalising it. This included
the declaration of religious war on Turkey in 1992, the
proclamation of a separate state – the Caliphate State –
of which he declared himself Caliph. With each of these
steps, the borders with the other communities became
tighter and harder to surmount.
The history of the Kaplan community can be read as
exemplary of what happens to a group which attempts to
translate the idea of unity into action more
consistently and radically than everyone else – and
thereby merely deepens the divisions. This was also the
view of some within the community. Mehmet G., a
supporter from the very beginning, who was imbued with
the vision of unity, told me that he had fought for this
ideal all his life – and was now forced to conclude,
that he had only contributed to splitting the community
yet again.
The party that Kaplan left, Milli Görü, went in the
opposite direction. Its mother party, the Turkish
Welfare Party, underwent a remarkable development in the
1990s. It transformed itself from a party of notables,
the main strength of which was in rural Turkey – those
areas where the Kemalist revolution had only partly
prevailed – into a modern party whose main support was
in the gecekondus, the poor quarters of the
contemporary big city.
This expansion brought new groups into the party,
producing two distinct tendencies: a reform wing, whose
principal interest was in social policy (and which as a
result was willing to enter quite unprecedented
coalitions), and a wing which continued to emphasise the
cultural struggle against Kemalism. These two wings
co-existed, and debated their differences at party
conferences. As in the German Green party, a first
revolutionary (fundamentalist or ‘fundi’) generation was
followed by a second (realist or ‘realo’) fraction,
oriented towards Turkey and life in Europe respectively.
Yet in both Turkey and Europe, the integration of new
groups led to a process of pluralisation and the
emergence of new forms of dealing with conflict.
Conflicts were increasingly carried out by way of
discussions and ballots and thus did not immediately
lead to splits.
It would be an exaggeration to say that the
Refah (Welfare) Party, and its successor parties
today, had given rise to a democratic culture of
conflict. In terms of practical politics there is no
clear relationship between the social and political
ideals of democracy and those of Islam. Necmettin
Erbakan, for example, stands accused of saying different
things to different audiences. This can be seen, not
simply as political cunning or hypocrisy, but as the
everyday attempt to reconcile an emerging ‘culture of
conflict’ and an ‘Islamic network culture’. On the
whole, the opening to a democratic culture of conflict
was marked by success, whereas the radical adherence to
the vision of unity led only to further splits and hence
greater weakness.
The self and the individual
These political experiences have also found a
theological expression, in the discussion of whether the
society willed by God is best preserved by renouncing
the ideal of its complete earthly implementation, or
preserving the ideal as a standard of judgement about
the fallen world.
The Islamic vision of the network society also has
consequences for theological argument about the nature
of the self in the Islamic order. Islam emphasises the
divinity (and thereby the social nature) of man.
Nefis is the principle of desire and egotism, but
also of autonomy, which causes him to forget his
divinity and social nature. In Islam, the idea of true
self-discovery can be understood in terms of
self-surrender.
This idea can be spelt out in mystical terms or in
terms of ethical rules. The mystical idea is more easily
accessible, because it connects to widely familiar
experiences. In the act of love, always the model for
the mystical finding of self, one experiences oneself
most intensely (and only then) in forgetting oneself, by
disappearing into or merging with the other.
Surrendering oneself does not, therefore, mean denial of
fullness of being – on the contrary.
Mysticism transfers this humanly transitory
experience to the absolute Other – namely God, to whom
access comes via one’s spiritual leader, the sheikh. The
unimaginable intensity of the self’s merger with God,
like the moth which flares up in the candle flame and is
extinguished, is expressed by Celaleddin Rumi: ‘For
where love awakes, dies the self the grim despot / Let
him die in the night and breathe free in the rosy dawn.’
But the idea of finding the self can also be
expressed in terms of ethical rules. Here it is assumed
that the true experiences of self arise only through
inscribing the law in oneself. Whereas in mysticism the
dialogic concept of ‘I and thou’ is central (and God is
experienced by way of the ‘thou’), in the ethical
variant the ‘I’ experiences itself by merging with the
‘we’ of the community. In everyday life, a ritualism of
little steps represents one technique for embodying the
law; another form of its incorporation is learning the
Koran by heart. In these practices the word becomes
flesh and the flesh becomes word. There is a beautiful
translation of this idea in so-called pictorial
calligraphy, in which a body is formed out of the holy
script.
The follower of ethical rules finds the way to a
sense of self differently from the mystic, but the
fundamental idea is the same. In either case, it is
evident that this concept of the self radically
contradicts the ideas of individuality and autonomy, of
the existentialist view that each human being is under
an obligation only to his own law. The tension between
it and the idea of the individual on which a secular
democracy is based is also clear.
This conception of the self was especially apparent
in my conversations with older members of the Caliphate
State. They were imbued with it; but at the same time
there was a break. These men were migrants from rural
Anatolia, who in their childhood had been socialised
into the Islam of the village.
In this Islamic life/world, it is easy to acquire the
feeling that the social order, the biography of an
individual and Islam constitute an interlocking unity.
These men had no or only rudimentary schooling. When
they came to the city, they taught themselves reading
and writing, and were seized by a real hunger for
reading. Yet this reading consisted mainly of popular
religious texts: the stories of Mohammed and his
companions, books about the Caliphs who followed the
true path.
Their reading opened up a world to these men; it gave
them access to a special universe. This went hand in
hand with an overestimation of the written text. The
printed word seemed to them to have a particular
dignity, superior to that of the spoken word.
Gaining access to the truth in this autodidactic way
– as is clear from the history of the Spanish
anarchists, as from the Protestant fundamentalists in
John Wesley’s circle – often produces a combination of
overestimation of self and political radicalism. Among
these men, there was a very marked scepticism towards
the Islam taught in mosques in Turkey.
When they came to Germany, they found in Cemaleddin
Kaplan someone who formulated what they had always
thought, or rather felt, but had never been in a
position to express – the idea that democracy’s culture
of conflict is basically un-Islamic. It is evidence of
the remarkable self-confidence of these men of the first
generation, that they declared to me their readiness to
break with Kaplan, if they caught him departing from the
right way by even one iota; and not a few did precisely
that, when Kaplan proclaimed the Caliphate State.
A generational shift: from autodidacts to
intellectuals
The autodidacts revealed another tension, that
between the nature of their religious search and the
content of their thinking. They professed the core
belief in subordinating oneself absolutely to the law
and thereby transcending oneself. But they had arrived
at this substance by a very individual route: by way of
reading, of criticism, of choosing a teacher. In doing
so, they had already broken with a world in which the
validity of these ideas was taken for granted, and not
subject to analysis. They had thus consciously
appropriated and reflected a message, rather than had it
self-evidently communicated to them through ritual. This
break would grow larger with the next generation.
The children of these autodidacts passed through
German educational establishments. My book on the Kaplan
community tried to describe how they found their way –
often via a rebellious phase – to a radical form of
Islam. Significantly, they often began to take an
interest in the community at a point when their parents
were leaving it.
The difference between the two generations lies in
the relationship each establishes between unity and
truth. For the parental generation, the idea of unity
came first. When Kaplan proclaimed the Caliphate State
with himself as Caliph, they left him. They recognised
that he was thereby abandoning his original programme of
a revived unity of all Muslims; they rightly saw this
step as a way out of the ordained network. More than
this, someone who leaves the community is doing the
devil’s work.
In other words, the first generation sets the idea of
unity above that of truth. More precisely, it had a
procedural perception of truth. Mistakes are always
possible; there is always someone with a better
knowledge of the never-ending tradition, and that is why
it is important to remain in the community.
The next generation had gone to German schools and
universities and appropriated Islam differently; that
is, cognitively and with modern intellectual tools.
These were no longer autodidacts, but young
intellectuals approaching Islam within a wider
perspective. The essential was separated from the
inessential; known facts from ones that could simply be
looked up (although one had to know where). In other
words, a hierarchical, organised, internally-structured
knowledge took the place of an extensive, networked
knowledge. Such knowledge can easily give the younger
students in particular, the neophytes, the feeling of
possessing an Archimedean point from which the world can
be understood – and from which it can be turned upside
down. Most people who have attended Western educational
establishments will recognise this feeling.
Whereas the first generation came to the truth via
the idea of unity, the second generation came to unity
via the idea of truth. What ultimately would unity be
worth, if it is established on the basis of untruth? The
second generation saw themselves as truly Islamic
revolutionaries. Here we see, therefore, another
decisive break in the understanding of self; this
generation appropriated truth for itself, and demanded
that the rest of the community follow them.
In a way that may appear paradoxical, the second
generation is much closer to the non-Islamic social
majority than that of their parents. It is noteworthy,
and only superficially a contradiction, that its members
are much more dependent on authority than their parents.
They admired Kaplan not so much as someone who
articulated what they had always thought, but as someone
who offered them a perspective, from which complex and
contradictory knowledge suddenly assumed a shape.
It was inevitable that at some point, people would
turn against Kaplan by appealing to scripture. For
example, in 1987 a group of Islamic revolutionaries came
together under the leadership of one Hasan Hayr. When
Kaplan made a policy shift – he began to modify earlier
enthusiasm for the Iranian revolution – there was a
revolt by fervent Khomeini supporters. The form of the
dispute was especially interesting. The group had read
and discussed writings in favour of the revolution, and
on this basis wanted to force Kaplan to take part in a
discussion. He refused and banned them from reading
these, to him, dubious texts. The community split as a
result.
A third generation: the longing for origin
The logic of this story is clear: at some point a
third generation must arrive on the scene. The
beginnings are already in evidence, where an
individualised access to texts is taking place alongside
a growth in understanding of the relative nature of
interpretations and, therefore, of tolerance (the only
guarantee of avoiding isolation of believers). Among
sections of formerly Islamicist communities, there are
now declarations in favour of an Islam that demands an
independent treatment of the sources, thus establishing
a capacity for criticism. Voices of this kind are making
themselves heard everywhere in the Islamic world.
This is the paradox of every movement which has
dedicated itself to a return to the beginnings, which
seeks to restore the relationship of individual and
society as it was conceived and (possibly) lived in
classical Islam – for inside the desire to go back is
also a radically anti-traditionalist aspect. Tradition,
after all, can be understood as growth, as disfigurement
of the pure, the revealed, the true; it obstructs and
conceals the source. It has to be uncompromisingly
brushed aside, in order once more to gain access to the
original. With that, a specific dynamic involving both
individual and society is recast: society is now seen as
a project, and the individual as someone devoted to the
truth.
The defenders of tradition have always pointed to the
dangers inherent in this anti-traditional impulse. What
hubris, they claim, to dismiss centuries of exegesis and
scholarship in the name of individual access to the
tradition; and, consequently, what a danger of falling
prey to demagogues, who in the name of origins reject
the legitimate, socially anchored interpretation.
Yet in the rejection of tradition is the same impulse
that marked the origin of our modern democracy. The
individual adopts a new approach to tradition, and
derives from it a critique of society. Of necessity this
often has severe, even terrible, consequences. At the
same time – and this is what I wanted to show here – the
internal dynamic, the contradictions to which this
movement back to the source gives rise, contain an
awareness and an admission of relativity. This creates a
new contest for the truths that are now individually
acknowledged.
All this involves processes whose inevitable relapses
can, under certain circumstances, lead to barbarism and
catastrophe. I am nevertheless optimistic that something
new will emerge from this ferment.
My hope is based on the history of fundamentalism as
a whole. Islamic fundamentalism could develop in a
similar way to Protestant fundamentalism. Over the
generations it might lose its inflexible, rigorous
character, and only through this loss gain the power to
shape the world. Such a point is reached when a religion
articulates itself in earthly discourse as philosophy;
that is, when it articulates arguments without reference
to religion.
It may be recalled that Theodor Adorno (especially in
his later writings), Walter Benjamin, Max Horkheimer,
Jacques Derrida, to say nothing of Martin Buber and
Emmanuel Levinas are Jewish thinkers through and
through, and that their philosophies derive their force
from the secularised reformulation of originally
religious contents. Today, it is possible to imagine
that Islamic philosophers could use the strength of
Islam to elaborate a philosophy of the network society,
incorporating a wise treatment of boundaries and a
rethinking of the social nature of the individual.
Copyright © Werner
Schiffauer, 2002. Published by openDemocracy. Permission is granted to
reproduce articles for personal and educational use
only. Commercial copying, hiring and lending is
prohibited without permission. If this has been sent to
you by a friend and you like it, you are welcome to join
the openDemocracy network.
Werner Schiffauer
is Professor of Cultural and Social Anthropology at the
Europa Universität Viadrina in Frankfurt/Oder, Germany.
He has written and edited books on rural and urban
Turkey, on Turkish migrants in Germany (Türken in
Deutschland - Eine Ethnographie, 1991), on Islamism
in Germany (Die Gottesmänner - Islamisten in
Deutschland, forthcoming) and on foreigners in the
urban context (Fremde in der Stadt, 1997). He is
also a member of the Advisory Board of Ethos -
Journal of Anthropology and of the Council of
Migration Research.
|